‘THE
NEW CLASS’ 1
(A
Review)
By
PHILIP SPRATT
At
the time of the second Russian Revolution, Kautsky and most of the orthodox
Marxists considered that Lenin ought not to have taken power but should have supported
the democratic republic, under which, in Lenin’s words,
Less
has been heard of this argument lately. The revolutionary regime has grown very
powerful and is spreading fast, and the protest that Marx thought it ought to
have started somewhere else is apt to seem a mere debating point. However, it
is more than that. Together with his scholasticism, there is much shrewd
political sense in Marx. Though his tactics were not entirely consistent, there
can be no doubt that the main drift of his doctrine supports Kautsky’s protest against Lenin’s opportunism. “New and
higher social institutions are never established until the material conditions
of life to support them have been prepared in the womb of the old
society...mankind never sets for itself any tasks except those for which it has
received the proper training and which it is able to perform.” Translated out
of Marx’s metaphysical language, that is sound common sense. Engels pointed the moral with an emphatic warning of the
embarrassing situation a socialist party wou1d find itself in, if it were to
come to power too soon.
Marx
and Engels argued that a highly developed capitalist
economy would have built up the pre-conditions necessary to central control,
whereas in a backward economy such pre-conditions would not exist, and the
socialists would have the difficult and unpopular job of constructing them. In
such a society the public would still be ‘feudal’ in mentality, alternating
between slavish submission and anarchic self-assertion; the democratic outlook
and habit would be ill-developed; the rights of the individual would not be
firmly grounded in public opinion and could be infringed with impunity; and
democracy would be an inefficient method of government.
Further, the proportion of industrial workers, the principal supporters of
socialism, would be small, and they would be ill-educated and without the
‘proper training’ to run the State and the economy. The
economy would, in any case, be unable to provide a reasonable standard of
living for all. In such a situation a socialist party in power would be unable
to fulfill the promises implied in its socialist slogans of liberty, equality,
democracy and prosperity. In order to stay in power it would have to set up a
dictatorship; in order to obtain efficiency it would have to permit extreme
differences of reward; and in order to develop the economy it would have to
hold down the standard of life and compel the workers to give up a big slice of
surplus value.
That,
in substance, is what Engels warned the socialists
against, and that is what Lenin, Stalin, Tito and Mao have found, is what
happens if a socialist party insists on taking power in a backward country.
The real force of the warning is not that a determined socialist
party cannot hold on to power and transform a backward society. It is that the
outcome will be only a caricature of socialism. There will be no liberty, no
equality, no democracy; even prosperity will be very slow in coming; but in the
hands of the ruling group or individual there will be such power as no ruler
has ever before wielded, built upon such suffering as no ruler has ever before
inflicted.
It
is doubtful if Marx’s exalted vision of socialism was realistic in any respect.
Even if the revolution had been postponed, as he desired, until capitalism had
fully “solved the problem of production,” it might well have failed to achieve
the ideal society he foretold. Whether, in the long run, economic socialism and
political democracy are compatible is highly problematic. Probably the soundest
conclusion from the experience of the past century is that, while the threat of
revolution may be progressive, its actuality is to be avoided.
That,
however, does not affect the validity of Engels’s
criticism of a premature revolution. A mature revolution might or might not
have done good: a premature revolution certainly does
great harm. We cannot expect a premature revolution to lead to the ideal goal
after a brief transition period. The direction of social evolution has been
drastically changed, and to get back to a world in which the liberal principles
are once more secure will be, at best, the work of generations.
Those,
therefore, who argue that the revolution ‘ought not’ to have
taken place in
Written
in a Yugoslav jail in 1956, and smuggled out and published abroad–the first
time that anything of the kind has happened in a communist country–The New
Class earned its author an additional sentence of seven years. As a former
guerrilla leader and party theorist he had been one of the ruling group round
Tito, and one of the top personalities in world communism, grudgingly admired
by Stalin as ‘a very frank man’. But, alone of all the men rvho
have reached such a position (M. N.
Its
purpose, however, is not indictment but analysis. It argues that the way in
which the communist societies have developed is to be explained in the Marxian
terms by the evolution of the communist party, or its upper ranks, into a new
ruling and exploiting class. Addressed to fellow-Marxists, that conclusion is
enough. Their theoretical aim is to abolish classes, and if he has proved that
they have not succeeded, he has made his point. For non-Marxists the
implications are not so devastating. There are ruling classes and ruling
classes, and though, even at their best, we may not like them, we are not so
impatient to get rid of them. What is devastating about the communist ruling
authorities, whether they are a class or not, is the way they behave to those
they rule.
Why
have they acted in this way, flouting their original high and humane
principles, and endangering their own regime? Djilas
says the explanation is self-interest, the corporate self-interest of the new
ruling class. As one of them he knows what he is talking about, and no doubt he
is partly right. But his own book suggests a different explanation, namely,
that the communist parties are forcing socialism upon societies which, according
to the socialist theory, are unripe for it, with the results foreshadowed by Engels.
Djilas is quite clear that
communism can achieve power only in backward countries. “Communism is dying out
or being eliminated in those countries where industrialism has achieved its
basic aims. It flourishes in those countries where this has not happened.” (Page 14). “….In Czarist Russia, capitalist private
ownership not only showed itself incapable of rapid industrial transformation,
but actually obstructed it.” (Page 15). “The countries
which were not yet industrialised, particularly
Russia...found themselves in a dilemma they had either to become industrialised or to discontinue active participation on
the stage of history, turning into captives of the developed countries and
their monopolies, thus doomed to degeneracy…In these countries revolution
became an inescapable necessity, a vital need for the nation.” (Page 11).
Some
of these statements are certainly false. Before 1917 in
It
is also false that communism triumphed in
However,
he is right to assert that there is a connection between communism and economic
backwardness. He also sees that there is a connection between backwardness and
the continuance of violence long after the revolutionary crisis. “In earlier
revolutions, revolutionary force and violence became a hindrance to the economy
as soon as the old order was overthrown. In communism revolutionary force and
violence are a condition for further development. Force and violence are
elevated to the lofty position of a cult and an ultimate goal. In the past, the
classes and forces which made up a new society already existed before the
revolution erupted. The communist revolutions are the first which have had to
create a new society.” (Pages 21-22). It is not his purpose to go into detail,
but he remarks that communist methods “are perhaps the most brutal ones
recorded in history.”
He
points out repeatedly that the backwardness of society and the consequent
magnitude of the task of transformation brought it about that the party was
uncommonly dogmatic and fanatical. “None had, before, the task of transforming
all of society. For such a task a complete, fanatical confidence in the
righteousness and nobility of their views is necessary. Such a task calls for
exceptionally brutal measures against other ideologies.” (Pages 76-77). He
devotes a whole chapter to ideological dictatorship, and reserves for it his
harshest condemnation. “A sword hangs over Yugoslav culture, but the sword has
been driven into the heart of Soviet culture. “The Communist oligarchy cannot
but accomplish complete corruption of the mind.” “History will pardon
Communists for much...But the stifling of every divergent thought,
the exclusive monopoly of thinking...will nail the Communists to a cross of
shame in history.”
Djilas denies that the labour camp system was mainly due to the low level of
technology. But since Stalin’s death compulsory labour
has been greatly reduced, and one of the reasons given by foreign students of
Russian affairs is that at the higher technological level now being reached it
no longer pays. The camp system continues in
Djilas does admit, in fact,
that “compulsory labour became too costly as soon as
advanced technology was introduced in the U. S. S. R.” (Page
111). It was only because labour was so
plentiful and cheap, and technology so backward, that the labour
camp system could assume such monstrous proportions. Even under the drastic and
ingenious compulsions used, camp labour was of low
efficiency, and the wastage of manpower was terribly high. Julius Margolin, an
The
all-round moral decline of communism after taking power is a puzzling
phenomenon, but most anomalous and surprising of all is the bad treatment of labour. It has been common in the early stages of
industrialisation for the ill-educated and inefficient labour
typical of such periods to be treated badly. The Marxian movement was founded
as a protest against this, and has always claimed to base itself on the working
class and to cherish the emancipation of labour as
its principal aim. How, on taking power, could it abandon what purported to be
its very raison d’ etre?
Djilas comments on this wide
gulf between profession and practice. He quotes a parallel from the 15th
century and remarks, “there is much of the feudal and fanatic in the dogmatism
of contemporary Communism.” (Page 150). The hint may
be worth pursuing. The mediaeval man, writes Huizinga,
oscillates “between cruelty and tenderness, between
harsh asceticism and insane attachment to the delights of this world, between
hatred and goodness.” In that era man expressed his
emotions in art more readily than in practice. The mediaeval noble solemnly
proclaimed his belief that his high social status should be the reward of
virtue: he commiserated with the poor, enunciated the principle of the equality
of men, and long before John Ball, sang “When Adam delved and Eve span, who was
then the gentleman?” In the same way he professed the ideal of courtly love,
while his actual sexual conduct was shameless. All this high principle and
devotion to Christian ethics remained stereotyped and theoretical.” “The soul
of the middle ages, ferocious and passionate, could only have been led by
placing the ideal far too high…” All this from Huizinga. Bryce writes on mediaeval society in a
very similar strain.
Let
us make what allowance we can for men brought up in a mediaeval social climate
which makes them schizophrenic. Still the puzzle is not solved. Lenin was an
honest and clear-headed man, completely free from sordid ambition. He was under
no compulsion when in 1903 he began to think out and put into practice the plan
of party organisation which, as he knew, and Martov,
Trotsky and Luxemburg also knew, would end, if he succeeded, in making him the
Robespierre of Russia. They called him by that name long before the revolution.
Stalin was under no compulsion when, long before Hitler took power in
Many
of the man-made horrors which have befallen our long suffering race have
resulted from quandaries, deadlocks, situations of Compulsion, from which there
was no harmless way out. The communist policy of forcing socialism on societies
which were not ripe for it did not result from any such situation. It was a
free decision, made by men who, as well-read Marxists, knew the evil
consequences prophesied for it by their own theoretical masters. Yet they did
it. Why?
In
Lenin’s day it was chiefly ideological fanaticism, for when they seized power
before they ought to have done, the Bolsheviks quieted their consciences with
the hope that world revolution war imminent and that socialist
He
does, however, refer obliquely to the principal force impelling the communists
to undertake their huge feats of industrial construction. He speaks of “the
senseless race of the ‘leading Socialist country’–the U.S.S.R.–to overtake and
surpass the most highly developed countries. What does this cost? And where
does it lead? Perhaps the U.S.S.R. can overtake some branches of the economy of
the most highly developed countries. By infinite waste of manpower, by low
wages, and by neglect of the other branches of industry, this may be possible.
It is quite another question whether this is economically justifiable. Such
plans are aggressive m themselves...” (Pages 121-122). “During the period of
industrialisation, concentrating on power could still be considered
natural.” But as all this is being completed, it becomes apparent that in
Communism power has not only been a means but that it has also become the main,
if not the sole, end...power is an end in itself and the essence of
contemporary Communism.” (Page 169).
This
ambition to ‘overtake and surpass’ the power of other countries is not new.
It
has not been sufficiently realised in
The
Indian intelligentsia in fact are yielding to the same temptation as Leain, Stalin and Mao: they are being tempted to force
socialism upon a society which is unripe for it, not in order to benefit the poor,
but to flatter national pride and to intoxicate themselves with power. It is a
project which cannot be carried through by democratic means, as Engels clearly foresaw. The first two years of the attempt
have caused increased unemployment, a fall in the standard of life, and much
popular discontent. It is bound to continue doing so, and eventually to bring
about the downfall of the present ruling party. If the passion for socialism
continues to animate the intelligentsia, the result must ultimately be to
transfer power to the fanatical party which will scrap democracy, ignore the
suffering and suppress the protests of the masses, and force socialism through
at any cost–the Communist Party. The only hope is that while there is still
time, the socialist intellectuals will read Marx and Engels,
who make it perfectly clear that a country in India’s position must undergo a
prolonged capitalist development before it can safely embark upon socialism.
1 The
New Class by Milovan Djilas. (Praeger, New York. 2
Dollars)