FUNDAMENTAL RIGHTS ARE FUNDAMENTAL

 

PROF. M. RUTHNASWAMY, M. P.

 

Mr. Nath Pai’s Bill, introduced in Parliament last year, seeks to amend the Constitution so as to give power to Parliament to pass legislation modifying or reducing the fundamental rights guaranteed in the Constitution. It is based on a misunderstanding of the constitutional position and powers of Parliament, and on the mistaken idea that Parliament is sovereign and supreme. For under the Constitution no legislature is supreme in India. The Parliament can legislate only within the limits laid down in the Constitution. Only the subjects listed in List I, the Union list and List III, the Concurrent list, in the seventh schedule

come within the legislative competence of the Parliament. And if provision is made for amending the Constitution in Art. 368 by means of a special procedure, it is only the Constitution that can be amended. And Fundamental Rights are not part of the constitution.

 

A Constitution, according to the Encyclopaedia Britannica in the wider sense, is the whole scheme regulating a country’s government. Jennings describes a constitution as “The document in which are set out the rules governing the composition, powers and methods of operation of the main institutions of government and the general principles applicable to their relations with the citizens, it merely sets out the rules determining the operation of governmental institutions.” If there is more than one institution of government it arranges the relations between them–between the legislature and the judiciary and the executive. “It assigns” in Chief Justice Marshall’s words, “to different departments their respective powers.” In the judgment on Marbury vs. Madison (1803) he acknowledged that “The people have an original right to establish for their future government such principles as in their opinion will not conduce to their own happiness, the exercise of this right is a very great exertion nor can it nor ought it to be frequently repeated.” He went on to say, “The principles so established are deemed fundamental and as the authority from which they proceed is supreme and can seldom act, they are designed to be permanent.” Now, the principles so established for the Government of India after independence by the people through their representatives in the Constituent Assembly are contained in Part IV, the chapter on Fundamental Rights. They are the principles on which the future government of India was to be conducted. They are not part of the Constitution which deals only with the mechanics of government, and the machinery of government. They are apart from and above the Constitution which directs the machinery of government, the working of its several parts and their relation with one another. Fundamental Rights are not part of the Constitution–not that part which can be changed by amendment according to the special procedure provided for it in Art. 368 of the Constitution.

 

Look at the place occupied by the Fundamental Rights in the Constitution of India. After in Part I defining the territory of India–the space over which the Government described in the Constitution would have its jurisdiction, and Part II which defines the people over whom the Government could exercise power, the citizens of India, comes Part III on Fundamental Rights defining and detailing the principles to which that system of government should be carried–the principles to which that system of government would be subject. They form the head and front of the Constitution. Their place in the Constitution frees them from the defect pointed out by Mirabeau, the statesman of the French Revolution who declared that “a Declaration of Rights without a Constitution to guarantee them is but the almanac of a year.” Fundamental Rights are placed under the protection of a Constitution which was framed together with the Rights that were declared.

 

And these rights and the principles of government which they enshrined are among the most important that have ever governed the life of free and civilized men. At the head stands the principle of equality–equality before the law, equality of opportunity, prohibition of any discrimination and abolition of the age-old practise of untouchability. And then come the freedoms of free men–freedom of speech and expression, freedom of association assembly, freedom of movement and settlement, freedom to acquire land and dispose of property, right to life and liberty. And then the rights practised in a tolerant State, the right to freedom of conscience and the right freely to profess, practise and propagate religion. And then the special section on rights of minorities to have educational and charitable of their own and for their own members. And on the great legal principle ubi jus obi remedium, no right without a remedy, comes the section on the right to constitutional remedies for infringement of rights.

 

This short enumeration of the rights guaranteed in the Constitution by itself proves the importance and the fundamental character of these rights. They are not granted by the Constitutionthey are guaranteed by the Constitution. Either as natural rightsnatural to all men to which men have a right like the right to life, liberty and property they antedate constitutions and even States. It is true as Bentham contended that it is only in states with Governments to uphold them that they are secure. But without States and Governmentsas in the West, in North America in the days of the pioneersmen would secure them by their own right hand or as best they can. In some countries, as in England and in India under the British, these natural rights are common law rights that existed and operated. And they have been treated as fundamental.

 

Even in England where the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty preached for a generation of English-speaking people by Professor A. V. Diceyand one cannot help thinking that Mr. Nath Pai is under the influence of that doctrine accepted as gospel truth in his student daysthe doctrine has begun to wear thin. In a recent history of English Law (Social History of English law by Harding 1966) the author speaks of a fundamental law in England. Fortescue referred to a formulation of fundamental law under which both king and subject had rights. The modern historic traces reference to it from Stuart times when lawyers turned to history to justify their view of the Constitution (that the king was not above the law) because antiquity was the only attribute of the fundamental law they all invoked. The great lawyer, Coke, who resisted King James I and was removed from office, believed that there were some fundamental principles behind English law which it was inadvisable for Parliament to alter. In Dec., 1641 in the Grand Remonstrance the Commons denounced the king “for a malignant and pernicious design of subverting the fundamental laws and principles of government.” In medieval times and in recent years Dicey’s theory of the sovereignty of Parliament has been called in question. There are many things Parliament cannot do. “No parliament,” says Professor Laski, “would dare to disfranchise the Roman Catholics or to prohibit the existence of trade unions.” Dicey was drawn by this inability to distinguish between legal sovereignty and political sovereignty. But then as Professor Jennings points out, legal sovereignty, which is a lawyer’s concept, is not sovereignty at all, it is not supreme power. And by legal sovereignty the lawyers express the relations between Parliament and the courts, the courts recognize any law passed by Parliament as valid. The political soveriegn is the people.

 

Modern English political thought also has given currency to the idea of certain fundamental laws binding Parliament. Locke argued that although the legislative power is supreme, even absolute is not arbitrary, unlimited. Legislative supremacy for Locke was not the right of a legislature to do anything that it wished or in any way it wishes. Bentham in his Constitutional Code (1870-80) rejected parliamentary supremacy emphatically and adopted the principle of the French Constitution of 1791, which had been advocated by Sieyes of a constitutional authority, to which the other authorities of the State including the Legislature was to be subordinated. According to Bentham the legislative power is subordinate to “supreme constitutive power.” According to Bayehot, to attribute sovereignty to the Commons is to misunderstand the power the Ministers exercise on the one-hand and the role of the electorate on the other. He also like Behtham held the sovereignty or supremacy of the legislature as being qualified by the power of a constitutional authority.

 

If it is so far a unitary government like that of England, without a formal written constitution, it is definitely and unmistakably so in a Federal written constitution. Chief Justice Marshall’s view of the people being the makers and amenders of this Constitution and the principles on which their government ought to be conducted which are fundamental and permanent (till they decide to change them) has already been quoted. Later judicial opinion in the U. S. A. has also gone on to confirm this view. Mr. Justice Black writing on the Bill of Rights in New York University Law Review April 1960, wrote: “It is my belief that there are ‘absolutes’ in the Bill of Rights and they were put there on purpose by men who knew what words meant and meant these prohibitions to be absolute as to the ground that a supreme public interest justifies the abridgement (of these rights). I think the Bill of Rights makes its safgaurds superior.” Mr. Justice Jackson in West Virginia State Board of Education vs. Banette said, “One’s right to life, liberty and property, to free speech, a free press, freedom of worship and assembly and other fundamental rights may not be submitted to vote; they depend on the results of no election.”

 

Against this cloud of witnesses from abroad what can the protagonists of the attempt to place such fundamental laws as fundamental rights at the mercy of a parliamentary majority, which is in fact a party majority, say? Only the Communists could support such a movefor according to them law is what the Communist party at any given moment desiderates. Socialists also may be tempted to support this viewfor these fundamental rights are a nuisance and obstacle in the way of their achievement of socialist ideas. And the present Government at the centre, which has so readily supported the move, has always looked askance at fundamental rights. But all those that believe in the right to equality, to free speech, free association, to free exercise of religion, as being necessary to the life of free and civilized men will oppose the move and prevent it from proceeding to the desired amendment of the Constitution.

 

Especially as they can invoke the Constitution itself in support of this stand. At the very commencement of the chapter on Fundamental Rights, Art. 13 (1) provides that all past laws, so far as they are inconsistent with the provisions of this Part, shall to the extent of such inconsistency be void. And Art. 13 (2) provides that the State shall not make any law which takes away or abridges the rights conferred by this Part and any law made in contravention of this clause shall to the extent of the contravention be void. And what is meant by the State includes the Government and Parliament of India and the Government and the legislature of each of the States and all local authorities or other authorities within the territory of India or under the control of the Government India. As if to make this denial to Parliament of the power to amend the fundamental rights this chapter provides for certain of these rights being subject to legislation by Parliament.

 

Apart from certain provisos of certain articles providing for the State to safeguard order and morality, articles like Art. 22 contain provisos allowing Parliament to legislate towards ensuring the exercise of certain rights, e.g., Act 22 (7). Apart from these special provisos Parliament may not amend these fundamental rights. These provisions for Parliamentary intervention which are meant to implement and facilitate the exercise of certain rights guaranteed to certain backward classes and not to deny or reduce the rights as the Bill in Parliament seems to do, are exemptions, that prove the rule that fundamental rights are unassailable by Parliament even when acting on its constitution-amending capacity for they are fundamental and therefore to be protected and defended by the Constitution.

 

Back