ENGLISH PROSE STYLE

 

C. L. R. SASTRI

 

            “Though I have been haunted by the gnawing sense of guilt ever since that Christmas morning when I stole a chocolate elephant from the Christmas tree and let my parents think it was one of my younger brothers, I have always been willing to embezzle £ 10,000 provided my victim was wealthy. On the other hand, my artistic conscience will never let me leave a sentence less good than I know I can make it by taking trouble.”

–The late Mr. James Agate: Bad Manners

 

            The art of expression is an art like any other. If anything, it is the greatest and the most arduous art of all. There are some well-defined courses of study for the other arts. Yet, with all these, surprisingly few persons, strange as it may, seem, are ever able to make a name for themselves. In regard to style, however, there are no recognised text-books: the guiding hand is nowhere distinctly seen. The writer has nothing for it but to fall back, in the last resort, upon his own resources, rich or poor as the case may be: and to make his spoon, or spoil his horn, according to circumstances.

 

            The word, “style”, connotes a way of writing. It touches, not the matter, but the manner, of a given piece of writing. It follows that the finest style is that which has the finest manner. The thought, the internal content, alone is not sufficient. As Anatole France puts it succinctly: “Form is the Golden Vase wherein Thought, that fleeting essence, is preserved to Posterity.” He proceeds: “Woe betide him who despises Form, for a work endures by that alone.”

 

            This, in my view, requires not a little emphasising. Certain reputed critics have laid it down as their considered opinion, as their unshakeable conviction, that the manner is nothing so long as the matter is precious: that the idea is the chief thing: and that style, being only a kind of outward dressing, a sort of extraneous ornament, does not, and ought not, to appeal overmuch to the serious student. One of my objects in penning this article is to expose the utter hollowness and absurdity of this theory.

 

Obscurity and Profundity

 

            It is high time people recognised that obscurity of expression does not necessarily connote profundity of thought. Every person that writes is permitted certain peculiarities of style to match the particular idiosyncracies of his mind. But it only stands to reason that he should not push these peculiarities beyond a more or less well-defined limit. All arts enjoin upon their practitioners some amount of discipline, of self-restraint, and I do not see why, amongst them all, writers alone should regard themselves as being totally exempt from it.

 

            The function of literature, I make bold to suggest, is to entertain the reader, not to puzzle him. Nor is profound thought any the worse for lucid expression. If the expression is not lucid, one of two inferences follow. Either the thought of which it is, ex hypothesi, the vehicle, is not so profound, is not so world-convulsing, as it feigns to be: or it is, as yet, not clear enough to the writer himself. Let us not be taken in by such arrogant pretences. There has never yet been any thought that was incapable, in the right hands, of pellucid expression. As Herbert Paul, referring to Jonathan Swift, says, in his admirable book, Men and Letters:

 

            Until Swift became a lunatic, his mind cut like a diamond through the hardest substances in its way. No sophistry ever deceived him. There was nothing he thought which he could not express. The pellucid simplicity of his style, both in prose and in verse, came of clear thinking and sound reasoning, assisted by the habit of daily explanation to unlettered women. It is easy to understand him because he understood so easily himself. A great deal of time is wasted by the ‘general reader’ in guessing at the meaning of authors who did not mean anything in particular. Uncertainty is tile fruitful parent of obscurity, and many people write obscurely in the hope that they will be thought profound. Like the subaltern who would not form his letters distinctly lest his correspondents should find out how he spelt, there is a class of writers who will not be plain lest the poverty of their thoughts should be exposed.” (My italics)

 

Philosophy and Literature

 

            In philosophy thought may be more important. Nay, it is more important. But literature is not philosophy. Literature may be many things: and, amongst these, may be philosophy also. But, in the process of being taken unto its capacious bosom, they are made to

 

            “......suffer a sea-change

            Into something rich and strange;”

 

and what emerges ultimately is literature, not any “ism” or “ology”. Thought, indeed, need not be absent from literature. But there it is more valuable for the garb in which it is presented than for itself. Literature consits of “what oft was thought but ne'er so well express’d.”

 

            Literature, in short, is of the word wordy. It is thought plus style: and sometimes, even, it is all style and no thought–if, that is, anything written or spoken can be said to be completely devoid of thought. The silliest thing expressed well becomes literature: whereas the profoundest thing spoiled in the telling remains outside literature’s porch.

 

            I am, of course, to be understood as speaking in general terms. There may, indeed, be circumstances that palliate even the molt atrocious writing imaginable. Authors have been known to exist – as Balzac, for instance, who was not guilty it would seem, of having written a single beautiful sentence in all his innumerable books–who have written in a very turgid and unattractive style: yet they do stand high in the esteem of litterateurs. But, I plead, they are only exception, and, as such, cannot appreciably invalidate my argument.

 

            Literature, then, by its very nature, by the very law of its being, deals rather with the outside of things than with their inside. As George Moore puts it beautifully in his “Epistle to the Cymry, included in his famous Confessions of a Young Man:

 

            “The thought that sustains a book is but a small part of the book; a thought is but common property, but the words belong to the writer, and he cannot be dispossessed of his verbal beauty any more than a sculptor and a painter can be robbed of their surfaces.”

 

            He goes on:

 

            “An idea is mine today, it is yours tomorrow, the day-after-tomorrow it belongs to the whole world; but a beautiful sentence is always the property of him who made it.”

 

The Simple and the Familiar

 

            Coming now to the practical part of it, of all kinds of style, the simple and the familiar is the most to be recommended. The simplicity relates not only to the length of the sentences but also to the size of the individual words. One cannot, to be sure, be always measuring one’s sentences with a foot-rule, or weighing one’s words in a balance. But the safe rule is to make one as short and the other as light as is consistent with felicity of expression. If there is no variety and, further, if there is no imperceptible gradation from one sentence to another, the reading will not be smooth and there will, inevitably, be considerable jarring on one’s ears.

 

            The writer must guard particularly against such loose, careless and haphazard endings to his sentences or paragraphs. There are authors that end their sentences or paragraphs abruptly–with a bang, as it were. There is no knowing where one train of thought ceases and an entirely new one takes over. This is a grave falling in composition: and even some otherwise admirable writers not seldom fall a prey to it. The sentences, considered by themselves, may be striking enough, but the writing taken as a whole, the tout ensemble, in short, leaves much to be desired. A well-known instance is that of Emerson.

 

Emerson

 

            Emerson’s sentences are, usually, extremely simple: though, it is only fair to admit, his thoughts are not. They are, as it happens, charged fully with matter. Emerson, indeed, seems to have profited immensely from the famous advice of Keats to Shelley to “load every rift with ore.” He suffered, in other words, from an excess, from a repletion of ideas. We may say of his immersion in them what Chapman said of Marlowe’s (comparable) immersion in poetry: that “he stood up to the chin in the Pierian flood.” This is all, no doubt, very well in its own way: but, unfortunately, when he came to the arrangement of those ideas he sometimes (as has been testified by quite a few commentators) failed miserably. Of course, his method of piecing together his essays is–partly at least–responsible for this. He would, it appears, jot down stray thoughts of his in a notebook and, when engaged on his essay, bodily transfer them (or such of them as were apposite) to it. Naturally, his essays lack coherence. As Augustine Birrell pertinently observes:

 

            “For, let the comparison be made with whom you like, the unparalleled non-sequaciousness of Emerson is as certain as is the Coregiosity of Corregio. You never know what he will be at. His sentences fall over in glittering cascades, beautiful and bright, and for the moment refreshing, but, after a very brief while, the mind, having nothing to do on its own account but to remain open and see what Emerson sends it, grows first restive and then torpid. Admiration gives way to astonishment, astonishment to bewilderment, and bewilderment to stupefaction.”

 

            My whole point is that, in such a style of writing, both the sentences and the ideas have an incorrigible habit of leaving ragged edges of themselves behind. They are not “rounded off” as they ought to be. They do not, so to speak, “cease upon the midnight with no pain,” but go on and on, as it were, making rambling noises in our brains when they ought, by rights, to be comfortably asleep.

 

Figures of Speech

 

            Figures of speech are the bane of most writers of prose. Aristotle, we know, put a premium on metaphor, elevating it almost to the level of a divine gift; and poetry, perhaps, becomes all the more poetical for it. But in that (as Dryden calls it) “other harmony of prose,” metaphor (or, for that matter, any figure of speech,) is not such a prime necessity. Nay, it is often a positive hindrance. Some of the most exquisite writers of prose have avoided metaphor as they would have done the devil. They have let it severely alone. Swift is a case in point. “The rogue never hazards a metaphor,” said Johnson: and right he was not to hazard it. What is good for poetry is not equally good for prose. “There is one glory of the sun and another of the moon;” and prose has its distinct glory, which, incidentally, is harder to be attained than the one appertaining to poetry.

 

Back