A READING OF HUMAN NATURE IN POLITICS

 

S. N. RATH

Lecturer in Politics, Banaras Hindu University

 

When first published in 1908, Graham Wallas’s Human Nature in Politics created a stir among students of political and social history; and in estimating the permanent impact of the book an eminent student of British politics once said: “I am inclined to argue that no English thinker since Hobbes had seen more clearly the importance of the psychological foundation of politics; and since that book, few treatises on this theme have been usefully written that have not been coloured by its conclusions,” Why did the book produce such an impact? In what way did the book open a new vista in socio-political studies? And, what is the relevance of Human Nature in Politics to the political problems, especially, those of India, of the mid-twentieth century? Such are the questions one may ask today on reading Graham Wallas.

 

I

 

The “curiously unsatisfactory position” of the study of politics in the opening decade of this century led Wallas, an active politician, to re-examine the method of enquiry in political studies. He found that politicians and students of politics everywhere were puzzled and disappointed with the operation of Representative Democracy, a system of polity which had been generally accepted by the nations of Europe and America by the end of the nineteenth century. In the United States it was becoming common to refer to the electoral system as “the electoral machine,” while in Britain, Wallas noticed that his own canvassers in an election said among themselves that the work of electioneering was “a queer business,” To explain the causes of disillusion and dissatisfaction produced by experience of the actual working of representative democracy, nearly all contemporary students of politics had turned to the analysis of the institutions in a democracy, and avoided the analysis of man. In Wallas’s view, the current tendency to separate the study of politics from the study of human nature was harmful, because it did not permit political science to grow efficient or useful in a practical way. Though pedagogy was improving itself by utilising the knowledge offered by the new psychology, the lessons of the latter were neglected by political scientists. Since society now enjoys new opportunities for a better life created by the mechanical inventions of the nineteenth century, politics would, in all probability, play an ever-increasing role in human affairs. As a consequence, the need for efficiency of politics, for the power of politics to forecast the results of political causes, would be felt ever more. And to increase the efficiency of politics as a science of practical implications would require the employment of a method of political enquiry which would be scientific as far as possible. This is, in brief, the theme of “The Conditions of the Problem,” the first part Wallas’s book.

 

The method of studying politics scientifically would be governed, says Wallas, by the subject matter itself, which includes not only political principles but also man. Man is ever engaged, by way of reaction to his environment, in invention of ideas and institutions, which, in turn, act on his life in society. The entities which man thus creates in the process of maintaining the political organisation of society are included in the material for study in politics. To be scientific, a study in politics needs to adopt, says Wallas, several general characteristics of the method of natural science; these are: first, observation of the significant facts relating to a phenomenon or event; second, the framing of a hypothesis to account for the occurrence of these facts; and third, deducing from the hypothesis general laws to explain the behaviour of similar facts or probable occurrences in the future. In the application of the above principles of scientific method there are, however, certain limitations; one of these, to which Wallas would invite our attention, is that the student of politics can never assume uniformity, or produce an artificial uniformity in man. Exact comparisons like those made in natural science, therefore, cannot be made in a study of politics.

 

Bentham and his followers, who strove to make politics a science, held that the motives of pleasure and pain were fundamental, and that these two motives established in politics, as well as in life generally, a rule of uniformity between man and man. The Benthamites failed to perceive that pleasure and pain were not the only facts about human nature. In their zeal for the pleasure and pain principle, they urged that instinctive impulse, habit, and tradition, were also forms of pleasure and pain. They did not see that calculation of pleasure and pain assumes a prior conception of the end to which human action is directed for pleasure, or for avoidance of pain, while in action prompted by an instinctive impulse there is really no foresight of the end. By his reading of modern psychology, Wallas was convinced of the inadequacy of the Benthamite standard of pleasure and pain in politics: “the search for a basis of valid political reasoning has to begin again.”

 

Political reasoning, says Wallas, must be based on a close observation of human nature in politics, of man as he reacts to, and reacts upon, the political entities that constitute his political environment. Like a biologist, the student of politics must discover how many common qualities can be observed and measured in a group of related beings. The facts thus collected could be arranged under three main heads: first, descriptive facts as to the human type; second, quantitative facts as to inherited variations from the type observed either in individuals or in groups; and third, facts, both quantitative and descriptive, as to the environment into which men are born, and the observed effect of that environment upon their political actions and impulses. Much knowledge of facts about the human type could be obtained from a study of modern psychology.

 

The old psychology has tended to explain human nature by a few simple formulas, and to exaggerate the intellectuality of man: the idea that every activity of man is determined by an intellectual process, involving a reasoned calculation of the probable consequences of each action. Under the influence of Willialm James’s Principles of Psychology, Wallas was led to study the role of the non-rational motives behind human acts. There are many acts, Wallas found, in which motives do not occur from any idea of an end to be gained by them; such acts are guided by instincts: “impulses towards definite acts or series of acts, independent of any conscious anticipation of their probable effects.” Because during the lifetime of each individual, such factors as memory, habit and thought, increasingly modify instincts, their non-rational character is not easily perceived. Nevertheless instincts exist as inherited dispositions, and are manifested in behaviour in response to stimuli supplied by the environment. A few instincts, which Wallas discusses in detail, because of their bearing on politics, are: personal affection, fear, desire for property, aversion to repetition, desire for privacy, racial love and hatred.

 

The part played by the impulse of personal affection in the success or failure of a candidate in an election is a fact hard to deny. “The tactics of an election” says Wallas “consist largely of contrivances by which this immediate emotion of personal affection may be set up.” The Monarchy in Britain though intellectualised by many organs and agencies, was strong because of its power to stimulate easily the instinct of personal affection among the British people. A swing in the electoral pendulum could be accounted for, not so much by a reasoned change of opinion, as by the impulse of aversion to monotonous repetitions of stereotyped political opinions and slogans. The desire for privacy was seldom appreciated, especially in democratic politics, where “privacy is most neglected, most difficult and most necessary.” Continuous lack of privacy in public life told seriously upon the health of public workers, particularly leaders. As a consequence, people who were otherwise able, but not for a life without privacy, did not often survive in democratic politics. Wallas would draw our attention to the desire for property also, because, according to him, the whole issue between socialism and Individualism turned on the nature and limitation of this particular instinct. It was important to realise that the instinctive desire for property was perhaps too basic to be eliminated, though the mode of satisfying the desire for possession could be altered in shape by replacing old means of satisfaction by new ones. The racial feelings of love and hatred revealed in international politics constituted amn important section in the total psychology of political impulse; they deserve consideration because they have an obvious bearing on international relations and world peace.

 

Till this point in his statement of the non-rational in politics, Wallas has attempted to throw light on those instincts or impulses which, even without our being fully conscious of their existence, actively motivate certain aspects of our political behaviour. These instincts, it must be admitted, do not exhaust the list of all human instincts which might, under suitable stimuli, shape political action of consequence or importance. But this criticism points only to the limitations of Wallas’s probe into the non-rational springs in political attitudes and behaviour; it does not refute the thesis of Wallas that every political action is not motivated by intellectuality or reasoning in man, that the irrational, or non-rational, plays a larger role in politics than it is commonly supposed, or known, to play.

 

This thesis would be better appreciated if we turn to Wallas’s view of political environment in relation to human nature. The political environment, like other aspects of social environment, has undergone tremendous changes through time; seemingly unaltered and old, parts of it are built of new habits of thought and feeling, and of new entities which are the objects of political thought and feeling. How these new political entities affect the instincts of man should be studied in order to get a complete picture of human nature in politics.

 

The significant political entities discussed by Wallas are related to the modern nation-state and the party-system. Wallas found that the prevailing pattern of analysing the state as an abstract organisation of human beings did not explain satisfactorily the emotional fervour inspired by a nation-state among its citizens. The phenomenon was easily explained when studied from a psychological approach. The new nation-states of Europe made their existence felt, and easily recognized, through symbols like new flags, new coins, and new national names. And as these symbols acquired associations in course of time, a modern nation-state came to hold a permanent place of emotional significance in the minds of its citizens. Through their symbols, the modern nation-states have become agencies of stimulating variously the thoughts and feelings of their citizens.

 

Within a modern nation-state, a political party, according to Wallas, was the most effective entity, for: “it represents the most vigorous attempt which has been made to adapt the form of our political institutions to the actual facts of human nature,” The majority of voters in a democracy were hardly aware of the, raison d’etre of a political party. Then how did a political party manage to exist through successive generations and enjoy the loyalty of its supporters in successive elections? The explanation offered by Wallas is plausible: as an object of thought and feeling, a political party was simple enough to be loved, trusted and recognised easily in successive elections. The emotional response evoked by its name was intensified by party colour and tunes. The feeling of affection thus generated became a habit which tended to exist irrespective of party policies and programmes. From this analysis of loyalty to party, Wallas draws two lessons which are of special interest: first, the policy and programme of a party has little effect on those whose loyalty is determined by habitual affection for the party; second, party leaders should remember that the organisation they guide is no abstract idea but an entity having an existence in the memory and emotions of the electors, and, as such, does not depend entirely on the opinions and actions of the leaders.

 

As preparatory to his observations on the role of reason, as distinct from instinct, Wallas next analyses the issue of inference in politics. Deduction of conclusion from observed facts was a necessary step in scientific investigation. Deduction involved inference, a process of reasoning logically to a conclusion. Inference in politics could be non-rational even though its rationality was taken for granted by the person involved. His personal observation of active politics led Wallas to maintain that most of the political opinions most people held were the result, not of reasoning from their individual experience, but of unconscious or half-conscious inference by habit. Habit extended its power in politics through formation of tracks of thought. Occasionally inferences were drawn from suggestions broadcast by posters, slogans and other contrivances used at the time of elections. Newspapers also had a share in the responsibility for urging the public, especially readers devoted to particular newspapers, to non-rational inference. In academic political thinking, too, inference tended to be irrational when drawn by deduction from broad, untried generalisations. Conclusions derived through such reasoning were unscientific, often absurd. For instance, the logical democrats in America argued that because all men are equal, political offices ought to go by rotation. The student of politics, therefore, has to guard himself against errors of inference from sweeping generalisations. Wallas would ask him to abandon old-fashioned deductive reasoning in favour of the quantitative method of reasoning.

 

The quantitative method in politics demanded: first, exact collection of detailed political facts; and second, the application of these facts quantitatively in political reasoning. Wallas shows that quantitative reasoning could be used by changing on occasions the nature of a question relating to practical policy. For example, on the issue between Individualism and Socialism, instead of asking in the ordinary way to choose “either Socialism or Individualism,” one should ask: “How much Socialism” or “How much Individualism?” This quantitative approach has an advantage for the student of political theory as well as the practical politician; the former could use it to explore the sphere in which each of the two, Socialism and Individualism, has an objective necessity; the latter could use this approach to find a basis for real discussion as to how much of Socialism and Individualism could be combined in one system.

 

The efficacy of any branch of knowledge could be judged by a pragmatic estimate of the ability or power it affords us, first, in understanding, as far as possible and in the right perspective, the facts coming within its scope; and second, in perceiving their probable consequences so that practice might be modified or improved further. To bring real efficacy in a branch of knowledge, its students should be required to make a conscious and systematic effort of thought in a suitable method. To outline such a method had been the object of Wallas in the first part of his book; in the second part, which he entitles “Possibilities of Progress,” the author studied the scope of rational reform in the practice of political morality, representative government, official thought, and nationality and humanity.

 

What should be the ideals of political morality? Should the politician abandon ethical traditions and adopt methods of exploiting the irrational elements of human nature? Should the student of politics view reason as the opposite of passion? Or, should he consider one of the two as superior to the other? Such problems must arise with a fuller knowledge of the obscurer impulses of the human personality and of channels of their manifestation in politics. In solving these problems, the approach which Wallas regards as correct is to aim at a harmony of reason and passion, of thought and impulse. “In politics, indeed, the preaching of reason as opposed to feeling is peculiarly ineffective, because the feelings of mankind not only provide a motive for political thought but also fix the scale of values which must be used in political judgment.” Deliberate, scientific education in the emotional and intellectual facts of man’s nature could gradually lead men to conceive of the co-ordination of reason and passion as a moral ideal.

 

While the political strength of the individual citizen stood in constant need of an increase through moral and educational changes, the democratic structure was ever in need of repair or improvement through a critical awareness, on the part of its advocates, of its current ills and drawbacks. Considering the operation of the democratic system in Britain in the first decade of the present century, Wallas suggested several practical improvements. While recommending strict enforcement of the Acts against corrupt practices, Wallas made a plea for holding elections on one and the same day in order to save energy and time, and to prevent hindrances to effective political reasoning. The practice of holding elections on Saturdays had the unhappy effect of drawing people away from their work in offices, farms and factories. This could be avoided by holding elections on Sundays, a day on which religious fervour of duty to God might be combined with zeal for the democratic system. Regarding the political parties, Wallas urged that in view of the growing aspiration for social equality, there was need for giving a share in the Control of party committees and local bodies to the rank and file of a party.

 

The efficiency of British representative democracy depended in no small measure on the permanent civil service which satisfied the psychological need among the British people for a second base in politics. The civil service was expected by the nation to function also as an instrument of effective political thinking. Its effectiveness in this respect was hampered by the narrowness of official life and a habit of narrow, departmental thinking. These defects should be removed, according to Wallas, through adequate contacts with other sections of the people, variety in civil service training, and encouragement of the habits of research and organised work among its members.

 

How can we promote international and inter-racial understanding? This question seemed to Wallas especially pertinent in the context of the peculiar psychological basis of the modern nation-state. As an entity of the mind, an object of thought and feeling of the people, the modern nation-state was a factor which had come to stay. In promoting political consciousness, nationalism had considerable value, but it was proving inadequate in solving many of the problems of the twentieth century. Nationalism tended to develop into national egoism and vanity, of White Man Imperialism, which overlooked the demands of humanity on modern nation-state, and contributed to conflict and war. The findings of evolutionists should teach us, says Wallas, that biological expansion and improvement of any community was to be hoped for not from ruthless struggle but from a stimulation, deliberate and systematic, of the social impulse to co-operation. This would hold good of individual nation-states as much as of individuals in a community. There was an imperative need of developing a feeling of affection for humanity as a new entity of thought and feeling. The value of stimulating such an impulse would be two-fold: first; it would counteract the irrational race hatred among nations; and second, it would promote among them a positive feeling of co-operation for the progress of humanity as a whole. In the development of this new conception of a man’s or a nation’s relation to the whole human community, reason or conscious thinking would be of great aid. The future of humanity, which could be anticipated from a happy co-ordination, in international politics, of the forces of reason and passion would not be unreal, for the different parts of the world are being brought close by modern scientific inventions.

 

Such in brief are the principal ideas and arguments of Human Nature in Politics. Ernest Barker has noticed in Wallas’s book “a fallacy to derationalise political society because it is not an explicit organisation of conscious reason.” Other critics, too, have complained that reason does not receive from Wallas the recognition which is its due as a fundamental factor in organised social life. Surely it was because of his attempt to persuade the student of politics to revise the nineteenth-century conception of the role of reason in politics that Wallas is remembered as a political thinker. We have noticed earlier in this essay that Wallas criticises the tendency among political scientists and politicians to “exaggerate the intellectuality of mankind.” The main argument in Human Nature in Politics is that the irrational, the instincts and impulses, play in the totality of human behaviour and thinking in politics, as in other aspects of life, a part which is greater than ordinarily realised by political scientists and politicians; that in the light of modern psychology, and of the author’s personal experience in active politics, the assumption, held by students of politics generally when the book was published, that political entities have a base in reason only, or very largely in reason, the process of deliberate, conscious reasoning, is not an adequate, valid basis of reasoning in politics. We have seen that Wallas also urges that politics, to become effective in guiding human development in rational manner, should adopt the quantitative method in reasoning; that reason can, and does, produce in course of time new tracks of thought, or new entities and instincts in man. Wallas is aware of the power of reason in making the human type better than what we find him; though reasoning is only one of the processes of the mind, in human affairs it is the instrument of progress, of new achievement in civilization. It seems to us that Wallas does not deny or minimise unduly the part played by reason in politics. In this connection one should remember that Wallas makes a plea for the idea of the Co-ordination of reason and passion as a moral ideal. This ideal is as old as the Greeks; Plato, and even more than Plato, Aristotle conceived of such harmony as ideal. What is significant in Wallas’s suggestion is the point that such a harmony should come neither from an assumption of the dominance of reason nor from a hatred of the passions, but from a sufficient realisation of the useful role each can play when combined, under appropriate conditions, with the other.

 

Another line of criticism indicated by Barker is that by his insistence on the quantitative method of enquiry in politics Wallas is running out of the arena of political theory into that of the art of the practical statesman. Barker seems to think that Wallas requires us to employ in politics the quantitative method of statistics. What Wallas really means by the quantitative method as applied to politics is that in an investigation, or piece of reasoning, a student of politics needs to take into consideration as many facts as to uniformity as well as variations in political behaviour as might be relevant to the problem under study. Since this is suggested by Wallas as a necessary condition of effective reasoning especially in the context of modern times, the method is, as we see it, a concern of the political theorists of today. Barker’s idea that theory in politics “studies the ‘pure’ instance” which has little to do with the political art of the practical statesman can no longer be accepted as a rule. A political thinker can hardly think effectively or purposefully about a subject matter without considering possible results of its application to conditions of actual life. Wallas is a political theorist in a true sense, for he has a vision of the future and of the ideal, and at the same time he enjoins us to study the habits of ordinary men in politics, for, as Wallas said, theory as a way of understanding must be effective or useful in a practical way. An exercise in theoretical speculation without meaningful reference to current political entities need not be regarded as the only kind of essay which deserves to be classified as a work in political theory.

 

Wallas is now recognized as a pioneer in the modern socio-psychological approach in politics. This method had been tried by Gustave Le Bon in his The Crowd, A Study of the Popular Mind, published in 1900; but the work was, as suggested by the main title, of limited scope. A more significant study in social psychology was William McDougall’s Introduction to Social Psychology, published in the same year in which Wallas published his Human Nature in Politics. McDougall drew attention to the supremacy of instincts and impulses over reason as prime movers of human action, but he did not study their effects on political inference, nor did he say how co-ordination of reason and instincts could serve to improve political thinking. Wallas was a pioneer in the sense that his book was the first important attempt to apply in detail contemporary psychological knowledge to the institutions of the democratic state. But Wallas was not merely a pioneer but also a rescuer; he rescued the socio-psychological method from developing into a cult of loose anti-intellectualism. The latter tendency was strong in McDougall, who held that reason was secondary and hence a servant of instincts and impulses. Wallas, on the other hand, did not regard human nature as a bundle of instincts and passions only; he recognized the role of reason in human progress, in the creation of new social entities. This point was elaborated further in Wallas’s The Great Society published in 1914; in it he argued that the instinct to reason as manifested in thinking was, under appropriate conditions, as original and independent in man as the instinct to run away from danger.

 

The Great Society was an attempt on Wallas’s part to supply some of the gaps in the investigations of Human Nature in Polilics. For in the Human Nature Wallas did not deal exhaustively with many instincts which, under appropriate stimuli, might issue in political behaviour. For example, Wallas did not study such instincts as sex, self-preservation, self-abasement and parental affection. And he said little of the effect of his socio-psychological method on the conceptions of Liberty Rights, Authority, Law, and the State as a type in relation to other social and political types. In Human Nature Wallas studied human nature in relation to political environment; the Great Society, as the title signified, depicted human nature against the wider background of society as a whole.

 

What is the relevance of Human Nature in Politics to the present day political problems? The relevance of the book in this respect seems to lie in its value as an analysis of the danger for all human activities, especially for the working of democracy, of the “intellectualist assumption” that every human action is the result of an intellectual process. The experiment of democracy in Asia and Africa is based on political values developed in Europe and America; the working of democracy in new areas has either failed or attained only partial success. In India, our three general elections have shown clearly how easily electoral opinion is moulded by non-rational forces like casteism, communalism, all forms of sectarianism, love of monetary or other reward, and the fear of the evil and the wicked, which tend to weaken a democratic polity. Disappointment with the political parties, which have deliberately aroused the less desirable instincts among the voters, has, in some quarters, given rise to the idea of a party-less democracy in India. Those who advocate this change, however, have failed to answer satisfactorily the question whether parliamentary democracy as envisaged in the present Constitution can be run without political parties. Would it be possible to keep political parties away from the village Panchayats? What changes in their organisation are likely to make the existing political parties better suited to serve the true interests of Indian democracy? These and similar questions await a socio-psychological probe on the lines indicated by Wallas in Human Nature in Politics. Wallas’s quantitative method in political reasoning may prove especially useful in solving, among others, the peculiar problem raised by the introduction of a scheme for democratic decentralisation side by side state planning of economy in India. A tendency towards centralisation is implicit in our planning for a Welfare State, but the clamour for more and more decentralisation of governmental power is growing louder. Both state planning and democratic decentralisation are novel ideas to the Indian masses; the psychological demands of a planned economy along with a decentralised democracy might prove too heavy for our people at the present level of education, political training and economic condition. We should approach the problem quantitatively, and ask: how much of decentralisation at what level of the planned development of economy in Indian democracy? Looking beyond our national frontiers, the problem of peaceful progress of humanity as a whole looms large before all. The race for empires has, in our times, been replaced by a race for nuclear armaments of tremendous destructive potentiality. The evil of national egoism has to be counteracted, in all parts of the world, by a superior faith and intelligent concern for survival and peaceful progress of humanity as a whole. How to achieve this end is a problem to be tackled by conscious and systematic effort of thought following the method which Wallas’s Human Nature in Politics has offered over half a century ago as an antidote to an overdose of reason or unreason in politics.

 

Back